logo

37 pages 1 hour read

Discourse on the Origin of Inequality

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 1755

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Part 2, Pages 141-160Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Part 2, Pages 141-160 Summary

Rousseau argues that human inequality began with the institution of property, but before one person could declare something exclusively theirs, humanity needed to develop ideas that prepared them to leave their natural state. Human beings began by responding to the dictates of nature, but over time different peoples would encounter nature in profoundly different ways as they spread over the globe. Some would live in cold regions, others in the tropics. Some would live near water and learn to fish others could traverse mountains and eventually would have learned to manipulate fire. As people became more skilled in dealing with the challenges of their environment, some would eventually become aware that they were better at those skills than others and would feel the first stirrings of pride. At this point, they would be able to draw a distinction between their interest and the good of the whole, based on an assessment of what they can achieve through skills versus what they need from the group. Rousseau notes that in the matter of hunting a deer, the individual will still need the group, but if a hare runs along, they might choose to catch it for themselves.

Inequality at first developed very slowly, but each new milestone increased the pace of development. At some point, they would figure out how to make shelter, causing fights over the most favorable spots and best building materials. Those who lost the fight would settle for property of lesser quality, and so from its earliest days, the institution of property served to rank people. The establishment of property also led to the creation of the family, establishing greater differences between the sexes and strengthening the affection between parents and children. Fixed habitation made life so much easier that people were free to develop more luxuries and conveniences, on which they became dependent for their happiness. Repeated contact with the same people engendered deeper feelings of companionship among them, and so they came to develop more sophisticated language and form settlements based on shared kinship and customs.

The establishment of communities marks the decisive turn in humanity’s alienation from its natural condition. The more people came to know others they constantly found new ways of comparing themselves. Even leisurely activities like singing and dancing spawned cycles of pride and resentment. As people developed a stronger sense of themselves, they came to think of both material possessions and abstract qualities like beauty as belonging to them and would lash out at anyone they perceived to diminish them. However, people were still fairly primitive, possessing a vague sense of right and wrong but with individuals reserving to themselves the right of interpretation and execution. Rousseau, somewhat surprisingly, refers to this period as the “happiest and most durable epoch” of the human condition, the “veritable prime of the world” after which all progress was actually degenerative (151).

The human race could have remained perpetually satisfied in its modest advantages over nature, but that golden age ended with the discovery of iron. Rousseau surmises, admittedly with no evidence, that a volcano must have erupted and left iron deposits, but he does not know how primitive humans could have made any use of it. In any case, the discovery of iron prompted the growth of industry, which in turn required a larger food supply to sustain an increasing workforce. Agriculture also strengthened the norm of possession by adding the factor of labor: what someone had worked for was properly theirs, and so the idea of justice took shape. Courts of law then emerged to protect the owners of property.

Industry and agriculture accelerated inequalities as some proved more adept than others and as people came to realize how important it was to possess certain skills to thrive in society. Anyone who lacked a skill found ways to pretend, and this created the distinction between reality and appearance. Before long, everyone was lying to everyone else because everyone was dependent on others: the poor needed wages, and the rich needed laborers. An economy developed, and wealth and poverty became institutionalized across generations. The rich were oppressive in securing their privileges and the poor succumbed either to servitude or thievery to bolster their meager station. Such a condition was unsustainable as it resulted in outbursts of violence and disorder, disrupting the foundations of the economic system on which both rich and poor depended. At this point, someone called for the formation of a political society to unite the energies of different factions toward a common benefit. Rousseau imagines that this appeal was highly persuasive, and people accepted it happily, without realizing that in doing so they were submitting themselves to permanent servitude.

Part 2, Pages 141-160 Analysis

Throughout the essay, Rousseau describes the turn away from nature as both a tragedy and an accident. Yet when Rousseau turns to the process by which human beings shed their natural state, the initial causes are entirely natural. Human beings were still responding to their environment when the environment changed, forcing people to adapt in different ways. Some kind of technological development was necessary for survival. Rousseau appears to concede, albeit without saying so explicitly, that the state of nature could not have endured forever since the world is always changing. This does not invalidate Rousseau’s argument that humankind was free and equal in its original state, especially since the inequalities that result from nature remain modest and do not translate into a durable social structure. It also proves that returning to a state of absolute equality Is impossible even if all artificial distinctions were abolished. The state of nature thus serves primarily as a moral ideal rather than a past or future reality.

Sooner or later, he seems to admit, people would have built shelters, housed their families, and competed with one another for goods and honors, reserving for themselves the right to punish an injury. This is essentially the state of nature as John Locke describes it, with Rousseau favorably quoting Locke that “where there is no property, there is no injury” (150). A sense of right and wrong followed the invention of private property. Since Locke regarded property as an essentially good thing that allowed for immense improvement of the human condition, and Rousseau begins the second part of his essay by condemning property as the root of humankind’s ills, it is very surprising that Rousseau would describe the Lockean state as one in which people were “free, healthy, good, and happy” even more so than in the purely natural state (151). While Rousseau’s state of nature was on the whole better, Locke’s has the advantage of being more sustainable. Natural equality demands a cooperative natural environment, while a mildly socialized humanity still retains a decent portion of its original equality while retaining the ability to make changes in accordance with changes in the environment.

The section on industry and agriculture is also surprising, as Rousseau admits that his argument is on weak ground. He states that the discovery of iron “hardly suits minds that are not already more trained than theirs must have been” (152), which admits that people must have been more advanced than he has so far described them. At this point, Rousseau’s argument undergoes a shift. Until now, he was mainly concerned with establishing the natural equality of human beings. Once Rousseau reaches the point where inequality takes root, his main concern is to delegitimize social order as it has been practiced thus far.

Once technology leads to the division between the rich and poor, Rousseau’s description is unmistakably similar to Hobbes’s state of nature. Both Locke and Hobbes captured something important about humanity, but Rousseau believes they mistook one stage of its development for its original condition. There was a point where society was a war of all against all, but not because people are naturally prone to aggression. Rather, they were trapped in a social structure that could only be reinforced or resisted with violence. Also, where Hobbes describes the sovereign as a neutral arbiter, Rousseau anticipates Karl Marx’s argument nearly a century later that governments are a tool that economic elites use to consolidate power. Opposing both Hobbes and Locke, Rousseau claims that the invention of civil society marked the disappearance of natural rights.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
Unlock IconUnlock all 37 pages of this Study Guide

Plus, gain access to 8,800+ more expert-written Study Guides.

Including features:

+ Mobile App
+ Printable PDF
+ Literary AI Tools